On
the Psychodynamics of
Organizational Disaster:
The
Case of the Space Shuttle Challenger
Howard S. Schwartz
How could NASA, an organization with a reputation for successful
management, communication, and great engineering
achievements, succumb to setting unattainable goals,
block vital communication, and engage in self-delusion?
NASA abandoned reality for fantasy. This paper examines
the organization ideal as a type of ego ideal and
the commitment to both real and fantasy organizations.
Implications of these narcissistic tendencies are drawn
for other organizations.
IN THE AFTERMATH of the Rogers Commission report
on the Space Shuttle Challenger explosion a consensus appears to be emerging concerning the causes
of the disaster. According to this view, NASA, under pressure to
maintain its overly ambitious
launch schedule, and deluded by their
history of success into thinking
that they could not make a mistake,
launched the shuttle despite the misgivings of lower level personnel, who could not manage to make their concerns about the safety of certain components
known to top management.
But while, as a first approximation, this analysis is
certainly correct, at a deeper level it raises perhaps as many questions as it
answers. For it leads us to ask how an agency with NASA's expertise
could get itself into such
a mess in the first place. For example, the schedule NASA set out to meet was, after all, self-imposed. At this stage it seems incredible that an organization like NASA, with its clear history of
successful management, could have locked
itself into a schedule that it had no
chance of meeting. And how could an
organization known for its own
communication have blocked the transmission of such vital information? Perhaps most generally, how could an agency which had demonstrated the
sober concern for facts that was necessary for its great engineering achievements have succumbed to self-delusion? Moreover, the popular account does not explain
what to me, at least, was the most
striking aspect of the investigative
process: the apparent contradiction
between the revealed facts about the
disaster and the apparent attitude, on
the part of NASA officials, that
those facts must be some- how
mistaken and that, somehow or other,
the accident never happened. Taken
together, these features form an
image of an organization that had abandoned
reality and chosen to live in
fantasy—an organization in which fantasy
had become a central organizational
process.
If this were the case, we would expect to find
that the problems of NASA were of a systematic order. Indeed, this is
the picture that emerges from the Rogers Commission report. We
learn there of a large variety of problems with the shuttle hardware:
brakes, steering, turbine blades, fuel valves, to mention only a few.
And we learn of shortcomings
throughout the whole space flight system: in
training, in maintenance, in spare
parts availability, in quality
assurance, and elsewhere. Indeed, the Rogers Commission strongly suggests that if the Solid Rocket Booster (SRB) joints had not been the cause of disaster, inevitably something
else would have been.
The picture of NASA as an organization that had
abandoned reality for fantasy leaves us with a perfectly adequate
explanation for the Challenger disaster. The physical world is not an
"enacted environment." It is not the external dramatization of our wishes and whims. On the contrary, it possesses a resilience and recalcitrance
which will mock the dreamer. An
organization like NASA whose
business involves dealing with physical
reality has only a very limited
margin in which it can indulge
itself in fantasy before disaster becomes
inevitable.
But having said
that, we have to note that every organization makes a product or a
service that has to be transported out beyond the capacity for the
organization to define it. How long, therefore, can any organization that has turned away from reality and toward fantasy exist without inviting
disaster? Thus, it appears that the
conclusions of our analysis of the
Challenger explosion may not be
limited to the understanding of a single
shortcoming in a single organization,
but may instead point to a general
theory of the features of organizations that lead to organizational disasters.
The question then becomes, what sort of an organization was NASA? This turns out to be, from the standpoint
of organization theory, a difficult
question, since it is not easy to see
NASA in any of the standard forms.
Consider, for example, how NASA made decisions. It is obvious,
in the first place, that NASA is not to be understood on the model of Weberian (1947) rationality, in which fantasy plays no essential part. But neither does
it appear that NASA can be understood in
terms of the model of the intendedly rational actor, operating within a framework of bounded rationality (March and Simon, 1958), in which fantasy may perhaps fill out the limited perspective that each actor employs. For in the case of NASA it appears that fantasy did not merely fill out a perspective within an intendedly rational
approach to the world, but in fact it pushed rationality aside and became dominant over it. Finally, we cannot find NASA
in a political model of organizations,
such as is put forward by Pfeffer (1981), in which
each actor rationally pursues self-interest and fantasy is used to cool-out the powerless. For here it is the powerful who are taken in by the fantasy, not the powerless. As Richard Feynman (NYT June 11) put it: "they fooled themselves."
This paper will use Schwartz' (1987a, b) theory
of the organization ideal to explain how fantasy can form the central
feature of organizational process. The picture that will emerge is not intended
to be a general picture of
all organizational life. Obviously, not all
organizations are like this. Nonetheless,
it will be a picture of a powerful
tendency that does exist in all
organizational life and to which all
organizations, especially those which
have had a history of success are prone, and against which serious and concerned organizational participants need to be continuously on guard.
THE THEORY OF THE ORGANIZATIONAL
IDEAL
The theory of the organizational ideal is a theory
of organizational commitment. On the one hand, it is an attempt to
understand how, why, and what it means for individuals to develop strong attachments to an organization. On the other hand, it looks at the object of that commitment—at the idea of the organization that participants are committed to. I argue that this idea of the organization, I call it the organization ideal, is not the organization at all, but rather a projection of the possibility of a return to the state of being the center of a loving world that constituted the experience of the individual's
happy infanthood.
Freud (1955, 1957) refers to the state of being the center of a loving world as "narcissism." In it, the separation of the limited, vulnerable, mortal individual from the infinite, powerful, immortal world outside is overcome without the individual having to give up his or her own existence as an individual. Anxiety, which is the experience of this separation (Lichtenstein, 1977; Schwartz, 1983) disappears. The person is perfect. He or
she behaves spontaneously and purely out
of desire, and the world loves and protects the person in his or her doing so. The world, in fact, has its meaning in being the loving reflection of the person.
Freud (1955, 1957) calls the projection of the
possibility of returning to narcissism the "ego ideal." If I become a person
of a certain sort, we are told and we tell ourselves, the world will revolve
around me and love me as it did when I was an infant. The person one holds oneself responsible for
becoming, on the assumption that if one does so, one will return to
narcissism, is one's ego ideal.
At this point we may make two observations which
may stand as the rudiments of a theory of fantasy as an organizational
process. First is that the ego ideal is implicitly a social concept. It
involves the reaction of others to me. They are parts of the world whose love I am trying to attain.
Thus, the forms that the ego ideal takes are implicitly social structures. When the ego ideal
takes
the form of an organization, specifically a work organization, I call it an
organization ideal. This makes it possible for us to understand the
concept of organizational commitment. Commitment to an organization is the taking of that organization as one's ego ideal. It derives its energy from the desire for perfection, for the end of anxiety, for the
overcoming of the tension
between self and other,
that narcissism represents.
Second is that the organization ideal, as with any
ego ideal, cannot be
attained in reality (Chasseguet-Smirgel, 1985). Attaining
it would mean overcoming mortality,
vulnerability and limitation. But mortality, vulnerability and limitation are existential facts of the human situation of each individual (Becker, 1973; Lichtenstein, 1977). This fact has the most important consequences for committed participants. Given their need to believe in the organization ideal, and given the unrealizability of the organization ideal in reality, it means that fantasy, and the denial of reality, can become the motivational base of organizational life for committed
participants.
For the committed participant, some way must be
found to maintain the fantasy of the possibility of a return to
narcissism while at the same time accounting for the failure of narcissism to return. One way in which this is accomplished is through what I have called (Schwartz, 1987a, b) "ontological differentiation," in which certain
individuals are thought to be more important
to the organization, and therefore
to be more the ego ideal, than others.
In the most general case, these
people are those who are higher
within the organizational hierarchy.
When this happens, the paradox occurs
that in the name of maintaining the belief in their own return to narcissism, those
lower in the hierarchy have to believe that those higher up in the
organization are indeed the center of a loving world. Then
organizational life becomes the acting out of the narcissim
of those in power—the dramatization of the fantasy of the perfection of the powerful.
We need to differentiate this phenomenon from the case of following the charismatic leader. Charismatic leaders, as Freud (1955) says, have a
relatively small gap between their ego and their ego ideal. They have preserved a large amount of their original narcissistic
self-complacency. In this case, others take
them, personally, as their own ego ideal.
What we are talking about in the case of
commitment to the organization is something else. Here, the individual comes to be
taken as the organization ideal by having risen through the hierarchy of the organization, a process
which typically involves giving up one's original narcissism. Here, it is the organization which continues to be regarded as perfect, with the individual attaining perfection
by becoming the organization. Thus,
there is a twofold fantasy here.
First is the fantasy of the perfection
of the organization, of the organization
as the center of creation. Second is the fantasy that high officials of the organization are embodiments
of this perfection since they embody the organization.
In the case of an organization like NASA, the fantasy
of the perfection of the organization is greatly facilitated by the
attribution of perfection on the part of society. Society elevates a part of itself as what it really is and therefore asserts its own perfection. This is
another case of "ontological differentiation," in which the differentiation
takes place within society as a whole.
Actually, in this case, it does not go too far to say
that the business of NASA had become the creation of the image of
American society's perfection. This provides an answer to the question raised earlier, how an organization with NASA's history of success could get
itself into such a mess. It appears that it was largely because of its
history of success, and the attendent attribution of
perfection, that NASA developed the "can't fail" mentality that
John Glenn and others have rightly associated with NASA's catastrophic
degeneration. This is partly an analysis of what it means to say that
complacency had developed. But in this case it is more than that. I am saying that
when the business of NASA became the generation of the image of perfection,
making demands on the environment for adequate resources by raising the possibility of failure
became impossible. Thus, admitting the
possibility of failure became a failure.
The second fantasy, which takes its organizational
form in the dramatization
that high officials embody the perfect
organization and are therefore perfect,
will be our primary focus in the next
part of the paper. Here, though, it
may be worthwhile to note the obvious
point that, for the powerful, the dramatization of their perfection invokes a great temptation toward
rejecting any who do not conform to the
story. It was after all, the pursuit
of perfection that brought these
participants into commitment to the
organization in the first place. In this
way, organizational power may become enlisted in the process of fantasy.
NASA AND THE ORGANIZATIONAL
IDEAL
This part of the paper will show how the
psychology of the organization ideal led to the explosion of the space shuttle.
Technological
Russian Roulette
The idea that NASA officials were playing a strange
game of Russian roulette is due to Commission member Richard P. Feynman. Here is the
account as given in the New York Times of April 4:
Dr. Feynman . . . said that typically in flight
readiness reviews, conducted a week or two before launchings, space
agency officials would "agonize whether they can go" even though the seals may have eroded on the previous flight. But then, if they decided to launch and the flight occured
safely, he said, on the next flight they lowered their standards a bit because they "got away with it the last time." He described the process as "a kind of Russian roulette" or a "perpetual movement
heading for trouble."
Putting the matter in terms of the theory of
probability brings out Feyn-man's point most
clearly. In the case of Russian roulette, with one round in the cylinder, the
odds are one in six that a pull on the trigger will fire the
round. If the round does not fire on the first pull,
and the cylinder is spun, the
odds are again one in six for the next pull
on the trigger. To some persons
unfamiliar with the theory of probability,
it may seem that the odds with each successive pull would be greater. This is of course wrong. But it is equally wrong to suppose that the odds will be less with each successive event. This is what the NASA officials appeared to believe. The question is, how can it have
happened that NASA officials, knowing
full well the laws of probability,
could have made such an error?
My answer is that NASA officials were engaged in
the calculation of two very different sorts of probabilities. Both
calculations were legitimate within their domains. The problem is that one of the
domains existed only in fantasy.
One calculation was an engineering calculation. Given what is known of the technology, it is possible to roughly estimate the degree of risk involved. It is probable though, that this calculation was distorted by the other sort of calculation, which we may call the attribution of agency.
In order to understand the idea of the attribution
of agency, it is necessary to return to the discussion of the organization
ideal. The organization ideal is an image of perfection. It is, so to speak, an
idea of God. God does not make mistakes. Having adopted the idea
of NASA as the organization ideal it follows that the individual will
believe that, if NASA has made a decision, that decision will be correct. We
may refer to decisions made by NASA, considered as the organization
ideal, "NASA decisions." In the case of NASA decisions, NASA may be said to
"work through" NASA employees. However, there would be another type of decision within the NASA frame of interaction. As we saw, narcissism does not return to the
individual in reality and individuals
recognizing this must know that they
and their colleagues are not perfect.
Maintaining a belief in the ideal
character of NASA, these people can
say of themselves and their colleagues
that they are not fully NASA, even
though the possibility exists that
some day they may be. Hence, if these mortals, these people who are within the NASA organization but are not NASA, made the decision,
it will be a different sort of
decision. Call it a "human decision."
Human decisions, unlike NASA decisions,
are fallible.
Now the question becomes, for any given decision
within the NASA frame of interaction, whether it is a NASA decision or a human
decision. Specifically, was the complex decision involved in the design
and construction of the
SRB seals a NASA decision or a human
decision? If it was a human decision,
engineering standards of risk should
prevail in determining whether it is safe to launch. On the other hand, if
the decision was a NASA decision, it simply
is safe to launch, since NASA does not make mistakes. Now if I believe in NASA decisions, the first question I ask is whether a decision is a
NASA decision, because if it is, I
don't have to worry about the engineering probabilities at all. And here the history of success is related to the
determination of probability. For, since NASA decisions are infallible, every instance of a given decision being correct provides evidence that the decision was a NASA decision. Thus, in this question, it makes
perfectly good sense to decrease the
probability of failure with each successful launch.
Why the Question Concerning the Effects of
Cold on the Seals Was Not Passed Up the Chain of Command
When the Rogers Commission (RC) determined that the
decision making process at NASA was flawed, what they specifically had in mind was that the questions
raised by Morton-Thiokol engineers concerning the effects of cold
weather on the SRB seals were discussed at a relatively low level (Level III) and not
passed up higher to Level II or I. It appears that a major moving force
in determining that the question not be transmitted upward was Lawrence Mulloy, SRB Project Manager at the Marshall Space Flight
Center. The retrospective reasoning in Mulloy's testimony
is interesting:
Mr. Mulloy:
... I did not discuss with Mr.
Aldrich [National
Space Transportation Program Manager] the
conversations that we had just completed with Morton-Thiokol.
Chairman Rogers: Could you explain why?
Mr. Mulloy: Yes, sir. At that time, and I still consider today, that was a Level III issue, Level III being an
SRB element or an external tank
element or Space Shuttle main engine
element or an Orbiter. There was no
violation of Launch Commit Criteria.
There was no waiver required in my judgment at that time and still today.
And we work many problems at the Orbiter and the SRB and the
External Tank level that never get
communicated to Mr. Aldrich or Mr.
Moore [Associate Administrator for Space Flight]. It was clearly a Level III issue that had been resolved (RC * 98).
On one level Mulloy's reasoning makes perfectly good sense. It was his decision, and that of his Level III colleagues, whether the specific elements in question were flightworthy.
We have to place this reasoning, however, against the fact that the discussion concerning the effects of cold on the seals had been heated and even acrimonious, and that even after the matter had been formally resolved, Allan McDonald, manager of the Morton-Thiokol
Space Booster Project and Morton-Thiokol
representative at the Kennedy Space
Center, continued to argue
vehemently against the launch. The
point is that, while in the formal
sense, Level III had the authority to
rule the SRB flight-worthy, they also
had the authority to pass questions on
to Levels II and I, which of course had
authority over the whole system. In this
sense, Mulloy's justification is simply a non-sequitur.
The real issue was posed by a television commentator
(George F. Will, I believe) who was incredulous that anyone in an
organization would take this
much risk upon himself,
when everything we know about organizations suggests that the most natural thing to do is to
pass it on. There is an additional element that makes the question even more
interesting from an organizational point of view. It is that Mulloy justified his decision on the basis of the
fact that there was no Launch Commit Criteron that
took account
of temperature and therefore none that forbade the launch. In other words, Mulloy rests his defense on the fact that he was
following the rules, which is certainly a familiar enough organizational defense. But typically, in an organization, participants
follow rules
to keep them out of trouble. Mulloy, by contrast,
appeared to follow a rule that could get him into trouble; not to reduce his risk but to increase it. He
did so, as we have seen, in a perfectly gratuitous fashion.
These facts make sense from the standpoint of the
theory of the organization ideal. If, for the committed participant, the
organization represents the ego ideal, then participation in the organization's
successful activity is thought of as a route to narcissism. Accordingly, there is a built-in tendency to take responsibility and to exercise that responsibility with a bias for positive action. The organization's achievements, after all, are only realized
through positive action. Thus, taking
responsibility for positive action is
a way of linking "I did it" with the "NASA did it" that
represents perfection.
Moreover, similar considerations in fact mitigate
against taking problems to a higher level. The
pursuit of narcissism through the
participation in the organization is,
as we have seen, linked to movement through the hierarchy and entails the assumption that the most perfect union of individual and organization occurs at the top. It is for this reason that
those lower down in the organization feel it
incumbent upon themselves to play out the drama of the return to narcissism of those higher up. Characteristic of the return to narcissism is the experience of everything being right and perfect. By keeping problems at a lower level, therefore, Mulloy
and his colleagues were not only
opting for their share of
participation in NASA perfection, but reinforcing the drama
of perfection by dramatizing to their superiors that everything was just fine and that NASA was moving along in its inexorably perfect way.
Nonetheless, as we have seen, the
return to narcissism is only an illusion, and while Mulloy
and his colleagues can believe in that illusion for their superiors, and in
fact help to build the very illusion that they come to believe in, their own
experience for themselves may contain the seeds of doubt. For if the perfect
linkage of individual and organization is fantasized to occur at the top of the
organization, this implies that, lower down, the linkage may be
incomplete. There may have been other factors also. Perhaps the argument with
Morton-Thiokol engineers had some impact. Here is where we see the
importance of the rules. The rules of NASA, in this case the Launch Commit
Criteria, represent its procedural body. In following them, Mulloy and his colleagues could touch, as it were,
a bit of the living flesh of NASA and assure themselves of the success of their venture.
The Reduction of Process to Ritual
The emphasis placed by Mulloy and his colleagues on the Launch Commit Criteria may be put in the context of a more general approach to NASA procedures which I think of as the transformation of once vital organizational processes into empty rituals.
Some evidence suggests that NASA was,
twenty years ago, a model organization not only in terms of its engineering achievement
but in terms of its organizational characteristics. Indeed, the NASA of twenty years ago appears to have
been a perfect instantiation of the sort of open communications, organic, non-hierarchical
organization that theorists like McGregor (1960), Argyris (1964) and Likert (1961) recommended.
The odd thing about this is that, in large measure,
the procedures which represented these organic processes appeared to remain in place. Thus, NASA and contractor engineers certainly had the right to question the safety of the shuttle and in fact they did
so (see, for example, testimony of L. Michael Weeks, New York Times, Feb. 14). The problem was that their concerns did not register as important in the minds of NASA management.
Perhaps the most tragic example of this was the way
the objections of engineers to the SRB seals, a series of objections which
began in 1977 (RC: 122), four years before the first shuttle flight, and
never ended, were disregarded by NASA management. But an example which
is stark in its clarity is the testimony describing the way NASA treated the
concerns of Rockwell officials about the safety of flying in the prevailing
ice conditions. The New York Times (Feb. 28) describes the testimony:
Robert Glaysher, a Rockwell
vice president, reading from notes at the time, said he had explicitly told
launching officials, "Rockwell can not assure that it is safe to
fly." ... he testified that Rockwell's position was equivalent to saying it was
"unsafe to fly."
And they note:
Somehow, the message never got across. Arnold
Aldrich, the No. 2 man in the shuttle program, said that he thought Rockwell was
expressing "concerns," but that he would have never authorized a
launching if the prime contractor had objected. Mr. Aldrich said
that, to his mind, "they did not intend to ask me not to
launch."
Several commission members said that they
were puzzled how a recommendation against launch-could be
mysteriously translated into
a cautious recommendation in favor.
The behavior of NASA management again makes
sense if one considers the theory of the organization's
ideal,
it is an article of faith that NASA, proceeding according to its essential
movement, makes infallible decisions. To the extent that NASA managers are
operating under the assumption of being NASA, and to the extent that the
form of NASA's decision making is followed, they think of their decisions
as being infallible. As long, therefore, as managers
"listened to the
concerns" of engineers and contractors,
the success of the venture would be assured.
The problem is that while the image of NASA making infallible decisions is part of the culture of NASA for its managers, that image provides no guidance in the making of decisions and helps in no way to insure that the specific decision will be correct. In fact, once the assumption of infallibility is made, it may even degrade the quality of decisions by impeding the serious and self-critical consideration of criticisms and alternatives. Ironically, this holds true even if the criticisms and alternatives are already in the system, and can be ignored on the grounds that they were formally
"listened to."
What becomes clear from this is that while the
form of decision-making may remain the same, its content becomes free to
vary and to the extent that the form is relied upon as a guarantee of
success, the content can become completely arbitrary. It is this sort of
transformation that Feynman is describing when he talks of the way NASA
management came up with
risk calculations:
He [NASA management] said he didn't want to use
a mathematical method. He was going to use engineering judgment. And
as far as I could tell, the engineering judgment, so-called, consisted of making up numbers. (MacNeil/Lehrer, June 10)
The Disappearance
of Pressure
The scenario that popular consciousness has developed for explaining the disaster makes a particular appeal to the concept of pressure. NASA was under pressure from Congress, from the President, from the news media, etc., and so naturally it overextended itself and tried to do more than it could. I have no doubt,
as I said above, that this is true.
What strikes me as peculiar is the
remarkable unanimity with which NASA officials
deny that they were responding to
pressure, or, for that matter, were
passing on this pressure to anyone
else.
From an organizational standpoint, what is remarkable
about this is that the claim that they were responding to pressure would
have taken at least some of the heat off NASA and put it on the entities
that were applying the pressure. But, strikingly, they did not take this
way out and remained insistent that the decisions that they had made were the correct decisions,
occasioned by their own sober and professional assessment of the situation. A
phenomenon of this sort simply begs for an explanation outside of the
ordinary.
From the standpoint of the present theory,
pressure is not apprehended because it is inconsistent with the idea of the
organization as an ideal. The organization ideal does not move because it is
pressed to move. On the contrary, being pressed to move is a
characteristic of the finite, limited, vulnerable side of our individual existence which
the idea of the organization ideal is constructed to deny. Thus, the
organization ideal moves because of its own internal causes. It is the
cause of itself— in the old medieval expression, causa sui. Moreover, the
organization does not need to put pressure on anything or anybody else. All it
needs to
do is to make its vision clear to others and, if they have intelligence and good-will, they
will naturally agree. The reason for this again goes back to the conception of the organization ideal as
a project for the return to narcissism. The world is a loving world of which the organization is center. All the organization needs to do is be itself and the world will naturally fall into line. There is no need to put pressure on it.
The phenomenon of being blind to the pressure one
has caused is seen clearly in the account of the critical Jan. 27
teleconference between NASA Level III management and Morton-Thiokol. In the
course of this teleconference, Morton-Thiokol made it clear to NASA
management that they recommended against the launch because of the
effects cold might have on
the SRB O-rings. The discussion was clearly
a heated one and came to a sharp
disagreement. Lawrence Mulloy said that he did
not accept the recommendation and
asked if Morton-Thiokol wanted him to wait until April to launch. At the same time, George Hardy, Deputy Director of Science and Engineering, said he
would not launch against Morton-Thiokol's recommendation, but that he was "appalled" that they
would make such a recommendation.
At this point, Morton-Thiokol management asked to
go off the teleconference
loop while they reconsidered the
recommendation. When they came back
on, as the result of processes which may be signified by Robert Lund, Vice President of Engineering, "taking
off his engineering hat and putting on his
management hat", and despite the
fact that there was not one engineer
who recommended the launch,
Morton-Thiokol management had been
able to change their assessment and had come to approve the launch. Even so, when they sent their written approval, the letter still brought
up the engineering grounds upon which they
had previously recommended against launch.
Now it seems to me that anyone who was in the
least bit sensitive to the pressure he or she was causing would have known that this was a situation in which pressure had been exerted. But the Level III management involved showed no sign whatsoever that they knew that they had exerted pressure. This point is made repeatedly in their testimony (New York
Times Feb. 26-28), and it also manifested
itself behaviorally. If NASA Level
III knew that it had exerted
pressure, and therefore that the resolution
had been political, they would have
known that the safety question had
not been resolved on an engineering
basis, and therefore they would have been worried about the safety of the flight. But they showed no signs of having been worried. Thus, Mulloy and Reinartz mentioned to William Lucas, Marshall Center Director, that Morton-Thiokol had raised concerns about the
seals, but they mentioned it in such
a way that Lucas had no impression that the matter had not been entirely resolved. Again, Mulloy and Reinhartz
sat for several hours with Aldrich
and Moore before the launch without ever mentioning that there had been
a disagreement.
Perhaps the fact that the January 27 teleconference
was the most minutely investigated element of the disaster is the reason that it also gives us the best
example of what the denial of pressure looks like with regard to the people who are being pressured. For it is clear, on the one hand, that Morton-Thiokol was under considerable pressure to please an important customer and go along with NASA's desire to launch; but on the other hand, it appears that this pressure was not
regarded by Morton-Thiokol management,
as opposed to Morton-Thiokol
engineers, as pressure at the time,
nor remembered as pressure by them.
Thus, engineers Allan McDonald and
Brian Russell, as well as other Morton-Thiokol engineers, testified that they had felt pressure, but Jerry Mason, Senior Vice President, said: "There was some pressure, but I believe it was in the range of what we normally encounter," and Joe Kilminster, Vice President for Shuttle Projects, said "I did not feel a significant amount of pressure" to change position (New York Times Feb. 26).
Evidently, the differentiation coincided with a
disparity in perception of
the way that NASA had redefined the
situation, from one in which they had
to prove that it was safe to fly to
one in which any had to prove it was
unsafe to fly. Morton-Thiokol engineers
evidently realized that the situation
was being redefined, while management
did not. Thus, Robert Lunden said:
We have always dealt with Marshall for a long time and have always been in the position of defending our position to make sure that we were ready to fly, and I guess I didn't realize until after the
meeting and after several days that
we had absolutely changed our
position from what we had
before. (RC: 94)
It appears that we have here, in the
case
of Morton-Thiokol management, an example of the dynamics Freud (1955)
associated with leadership. For Freud,
the leader takes the place of the
follower's ego ideal. In the course of
this, the individual's sense of
judgment, his or her sense of criticism,
is given over to the leader. The
sense of moral autonomy is lost.
With regard to the Morton-Thiokol engineers, this had not happened, or at least not to the same extent. This is why the Morton-Thiokol engineers felt pressure, while the managers did not. The experience of pressure involves a sense of oneself as a distinct entity against another distinct entity. For the engineers, this remained the case. They maintained a sense of their authority by retaining their own ego ideal—an ego ideal in which their
professional engineering standards played a large part. For the managers, however, putting NASA in the place of
their ego ideal meant, in effect,
that they had taken NASA as their
image of what they should be, the realization of their own narcissism, themselves. In this way, the boundaries between them and NASA vanished. They fused with NASA and gave up their sense of being distinct entities. In effect, these people had given up their own selfhood. There was no self that could have experienced pressure.
Similar considerations apply to the question of why the
engineers felt that the situation had been redefined to require proof of why it was dangerous to launch. This is a question that makes sense only if the issue being discussed is one of launch safety—an
engineering issue. But for management,
this does not appear to have been
the question. The institutional
question, the management issue, as
they saw it, was how to please NASA,
how to confirm NASA's narcissism, and while the details of this may have shifted, the
primary task remained the same. It is
thus to be noted that when Bob Lund
"took off his engineer's hat
and put on his manager's hat"
the issue for him was already
decided. Indeed, once Mason announced that a "management decision" would have to be made, the issue was already decided and further disagreement on engineering grounds became irrelevant. Only engineers Roger Boisjoly and Arnold Thompson recognized that once the management orientation had been adopted, the discussion was over and the engineering question had become
irrelevant. Boisjoly's
testimony is useful in providing a
sense of how this felt:
Okay, the caucus started by Mr. Mason stating a management decision was necessary. Those of us who opposed the launch continued to speak out . . . And we were attempting to go back and rereview and try to make clear what we were trying to get across, and we
couldn't understand why it was going to be reversed.
So we spoke out and tried to explain once again the effects of low temperature. Arnie
actually got up from his position
which was down the table, and walked
up to the table and put a quarter pad down in front of the table, in front of
the management folks, and tried to
sketch once again what his concern
was with the joint, and when he
realized he wasn't getting through,
he just stopped.
I tried once more with the photos. I grabbed the photos, and I went up and
discussed the photos once again and tried to make the point that it was my opinion from
actual observations that temperature was indeed a discriminator and
we should not ignore the physical evidence that we had observed ... I also stopped
when it was apparent that I couldn't get anybody to listen. (RC: 92)
The Denial of
Disaster
Often, the organization manages to respond to
external pressures while still maintaining the idea of itself as causa sui by generating a
fantasy which rationalizes the actions it is being forced to take in a way that
still leaves
it with the concept of its own control. Thus, in a classic study, Festinger, Riecken and Schacter (1956) observed
what happened to a sect that had predicted the end of the world at a
specific time as that time approached:
a revelation! The world had been spared as a
result of the sect's activities and
the sect had been charged with the
responsibility of preaching this good
news.
In the case of NASA, as we have seen, the dominant fantasy had
been the fantasy of NASA's infallibility subject to the following of its forms
and rituals. If the forms were followed,
success was assured, and it then became the responsibility of critics to prove
that NASA should not act, rather than for them to prove that it should.
This is clearly shown in the testimony of Morton-Thiokol engineers.
It seems to me to be this flight into
fantasy that is responsible for the most remarkable aspect of the public testimony concerning
the disaster—NASA management's apparent belief that they made the
right decision. The only way this belief can be maintained is by supposing that
making the right decision means making the decision in the right way,
regardless of consequences. This is the impression many of these NASA managers
give. Thus, as only one example, William Lucas said: "I'm not sure what Mr. Rogers means in terms of
the decision process being flawed." (This Week with David Brinkley, June 8). The
differentiation between NASA management's infallibility fantasy and reality was sufficiently jarring to
become itself a focus of public discussion. Thus, according to the New York
Times of March 17:
One Marshall manager confided that he was
embarrassed to hear the center's officials contending that the decision
making process leading to
the launching was "sound."
"The shuttle blew up and you had
pieces falling from the sky," he noted. "How could it not be flawed?"
CONCLUSION: THE
NARCISSISTIC ORGANIZATION AND THE DENIAL OF REALITY
Throughout this account, one fact has remained
constant. Everywhere we have looked we have seen a movement on the part of
NASA officials away from
reality and toward a fantasy world. I have
argued that the fantasy world had a structure. It was a loving world of which NASA was the center and in
which individuals could participate
by becoming NASA. In this way they
could themselves become the center of a loving world. In a word, NASA had become a project for the return to narcissism.
Ultimately this led, as it had to lead, to disaster. For
the world that NASA lived in was not made to love NASA, and eventually
NASA, and the rest of us,
had to find that out.
Two questions that remain for us to deal with in
this conclusion are the questions of generalizability and treatment: How
widespread are these narcissistic tendencies in organizations and what can be
done about them? The answer to the first question is relatively simple.
It should be clear that the processes that we observed in NASA are by no
means confined to that organization. I believe that any participant in
organizations will have recognized at least some of them as being very close
to processes in his or her own organizational life. That this should be so
follows from the theory. The
desire to return to narcissism, to be at
the same time spontaneous and certain,
separate and connected—to be, like
God, all-powerful and all-good, is a
potent desire. I have no doubt that
if there were no such thing as
reality, narcissism would dominate all
of our psychological life. Of course this is an absurd thought. But let
me end the discussion of generalizability by suggesting that organizations represent, as multipliers of power and binders of opinion, social forces through which humans attempt to take control over reality. To the extent that this is so, it seems to me, narcissistic processes such as those I have described must be powerful forces within them.
The question of what to do about these
tendencies is far more complex, because
it implicitly raises the question of
what could constitute organizational
action in a therapeutic program of
this sort. Two possibilities come to mind, and we shall see that both are inadequate. But by understanding how they are inadequate we may come to a better understanding of what the problem is and it is this that may give us help in knowing what to do about it.
First is what may be called the solution through
structure. Change the organization's structure, in some way, and the problems
will be taken care of. This appears to be the basic solution that the
Rogers Commission recommended. There should be more central
accountability, the Program Manager should have more authority, astronauts should be in
management, there should be a shuttle safety panel, and so on and so forth. The problem with all of these
is not that they would not
be desirable, at least in the short run, but
that they do not address the central
issue, and therefore, in the long run, run the risk of becoming part of the problem. Thus, what we have seen is that vital organizational processes
tend to become ritualized. Rather than
solutions to problems, they become
excuses for avoiding problems.
Thus, as a procedural safeguard, Morton-Thiokol had
to sign off on the launch. But when NASA put the pressure on they
signed off quickly enough. And when the shuttle blew up and NASA was
called before the Rogers Commission, they had that signature to wave.
You can't blame us, NASA said, Morton-Thiokol said it was safe to launch.
The second possibility may be called the solution
through culture. The New
York Times of June 10
reported this:
Some senior NASA officials have conceded
that as much as changing personnel, the agency needs to instill a new "culture" in which
lower-level managers and engineers feel freer to communicate "bad
news," such as the poor O-ring performance, to key decision makers.
They said such a culture existed during the Apollo project, which was clearly defined as a
research and development undertaking and in which problem-solving
was an accepted part of the process.
The difficulty with this approach is
that,
as regards NASA management at least, NASA's culture was already fine. In the case
of communicating bad news, for example, numerous NASA managers
testified repeatedly that this was part of the NASA culture. The only
problem was that while it may have been part of NASA culture—the way in
which NASA saw and understood its activities—the culture had no relationship to the truth.
We see this most clearly in the case of
NASA's concern for safety. Public statements of NASA officials have so often stressed
NASA's concern for safety that if one did not know about the explosion of
the space shuttle, one could never have suspected that it happened. But at the
time that this supposedly safety-conscious NASA was acting to make sure that no unnecessary
risk could take place, they were cutting their safety budget by half a billion
dollars (New York Times April 24) and their quality control staff by
70% (New York Times May 8).
Argyris and Schon
(1974) refer to the way that an
organization's culture can be unrelated to its reality by distinguishing between a manager's "espoused
theory" and his or her "theory-in-use." They point out that one does not
typically have any relationship to the other. The theory of the organization ideal provides a complementary perspective. Here, the organization's culture provides the framework within
which the actions of
those in power are
justified. From this point of view, what the specific culture is, is of secondary significance. What is important is that organizational participants, both lower and, especially, upper, have a stake in seeing that the
justificatory process
takes place, no matter what
the facts are. This is the point at which fantasy gains the upper hand. The idea of bringing reality back in by changing the content of the fantasy
is, of course, absurd.
Thus, neither the structural nor the cultural solution are
likely to avail. A deeper look into the theory of the organization ideal
shows why this must be so. The point
is that, from the
standpoint of the theory of the organizational ideal, the basic problem that gives rise to the narcissistic fantasy which may structure an organization, and to the disaster which may result, is not a psychological problem, or a sociological problem: it is an existential problem. Existential problems are never solved; the best one can do is to live with them. The idea of "solving" them is already a fantasy.
The Greeks, for whom the term hubris described the
conditions we have found in the soul of NASA, evidently knew this better than we do.
Why we should have come to think that we could solve such problems through
technology or through organization is a question that goes to the root of the
tragedy that we have found.
REFERENCES
Argyric, Chris. Integrating
the Individual and the Organization.
Argyris,
Chris and Donald A. Schon. Theory in Practice.
Becker, Ernest. The
Denial of Death.
Chasseguet-Smirgel, Janine. The
Ego Ideal: A Psychoanalytic Essay on the Malady of the Ideal.
Freud, Sigmund. Group
Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego. (Standard
edition, Volume 18.)
Freud, Sigmund. On Narcissism: An
Introduction. (Standard edition, Volume 14.)
Litchtenstein, Heinz. The Dilemma of Human Identity.
Likert, Rensis. New Patterns of Management.
March, James G. and
Herbert A. Simon. Organizations.
McGregor, Douglas. The Human Side of
Pfeffer, Jeffrey. Power in Organizations.
Pitman, 1981.
Report of the Presidential Commission
on the Space Shuttle Challenger Accident,
Schwartz, Howard S. "Maslow and the Hierarchical Enactment of
Organizational Reality," Human Relations, 36 (10), 933-956, 1983.
Schwartz, Howard S. "The
Usefulness of Myth and the Myth of Usefulness: A Dilemma for the Applied
Organizational Scientist," Journal of Management, 11 (1), 31-42,
1985.
Schwartz, Howard S. "On the
Psychodynamics of Organizational Totalitariaism." Journal of Management, 13(1), 38-51, 1987a.
Schwartz, Howard S. "Antisocial
Actions of Committed Organizational Participants: An Existential Psychoanalytic Perspective," Organization Studies.
8 (4),
1987b (in
press).
* Report
of the Presidential Commission on the Space Shuttle
Challenger Accident, Volume I.